Well-ordered Cartesian product in ZFTransfinite Induction and the Axiom of ChoiceProving properties of...
Well-ordered Cartesian product in ZF
Why do Martians have to wear space helmets?
Can you create a free-floating MASYU puzzle?
Possibility to correct pitch from digital versions of records with the hole not centered
Wouldn't putting an electronic key inside a small Faraday cage render it completely useless?
My professor has told me he will be the corresponding author. Will it hurt my future career?
Why does mean tend be more stable in different samples than median?
Why is there paternal, for fatherly, fraternal, for brotherly, but no similar word for sons?
Is it acceptable that I plot a time-series figure with years increasing from right to left?
Shipped package arrived - didn't order, possible scam?
What was the significance of Spider-Man: Far From Home being an MCU Phase 3 film instead of a Phase 4 film?
Taking advantage when HR forgets to communicate the rules
How do I check that users don't write down their passwords?
Why do we need a bootloader separate from our application program in microcontrollers?
Bringing coumarin-containing liquor into the USA
Initializing variables in an "if" statement
What do I need to see before Spider-Man: Far From Home?
How to deal with a Murder Hobo Paladin?
Any way to meet code with 40.7% or 40.44% conduit fill?
Gory anime with pink haired girl escaping an asylum
Are "confidant" and "confident" homophones?
As a supervisor, what feedback would you expect from a PhD who quits?
What's the difference between a type and a kind?
Is conquering your neighbors to fight a greater enemy a valid strategy?
Well-ordered Cartesian product in ZF
Transfinite Induction and the Axiom of ChoiceProving properties of enumeration of infinite cardinalsAC iff $P(delta)$ can be well-ordered for all $deltain{bf On}$Prove using transfinite induction that if ordinals $alpha$ and $beta$ are countable, then so is $alpha + beta$.Trying to understand the sum of ordinalsTransfinite induction on class of ordinals.Shrinking a family of sets preserving cardinalityOrdinals and the Von Neumann universeOrdinal addition proof involving $0$Show that ordinal addition is associativeWell-ordered sets are order-isomorphic to a unique ordinal and proof by induction over the ordinals
.everyoneloves__top-leaderboard:empty,.everyoneloves__mid-leaderboard:empty,.everyoneloves__bot-mid-leaderboard:empty{ margin-bottom:0;
}
$begingroup$
Can it be proved in ZF that the product $prod_{alpha < kappa} S_alpha$ is nonempty given${ S_alpha }_{alpha < kappa}$ a family of nonempty set and $kappa > 0$ is an ordinal?
It seems possible with transfinite induction, yet I cannot seems to show the limit case holds for the predicate $varphi(alpha) := exists f (f text{ is a choice function for} { S_beta }_{beta < alpha})$
set-theory axiom-of-choice ordinals
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Can it be proved in ZF that the product $prod_{alpha < kappa} S_alpha$ is nonempty given${ S_alpha }_{alpha < kappa}$ a family of nonempty set and $kappa > 0$ is an ordinal?
It seems possible with transfinite induction, yet I cannot seems to show the limit case holds for the predicate $varphi(alpha) := exists f (f text{ is a choice function for} { S_beta }_{beta < alpha})$
set-theory axiom-of-choice ordinals
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
I realize that this might be a duplicate of math.stackexchange.com/questions/7065/…, let me know if it is.
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila♦
8 hours ago
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Can it be proved in ZF that the product $prod_{alpha < kappa} S_alpha$ is nonempty given${ S_alpha }_{alpha < kappa}$ a family of nonempty set and $kappa > 0$ is an ordinal?
It seems possible with transfinite induction, yet I cannot seems to show the limit case holds for the predicate $varphi(alpha) := exists f (f text{ is a choice function for} { S_beta }_{beta < alpha})$
set-theory axiom-of-choice ordinals
$endgroup$
Can it be proved in ZF that the product $prod_{alpha < kappa} S_alpha$ is nonempty given${ S_alpha }_{alpha < kappa}$ a family of nonempty set and $kappa > 0$ is an ordinal?
It seems possible with transfinite induction, yet I cannot seems to show the limit case holds for the predicate $varphi(alpha) := exists f (f text{ is a choice function for} { S_beta }_{beta < alpha})$
set-theory axiom-of-choice ordinals
set-theory axiom-of-choice ordinals
edited 8 hours ago
Asaf Karagila♦
313k34 gold badges448 silver badges782 bronze badges
313k34 gold badges448 silver badges782 bronze badges
asked 8 hours ago
Vinh KhangVinh Khang
1067 bronze badges
1067 bronze badges
$begingroup$
I realize that this might be a duplicate of math.stackexchange.com/questions/7065/…, let me know if it is.
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila♦
8 hours ago
add a comment |
$begingroup$
I realize that this might be a duplicate of math.stackexchange.com/questions/7065/…, let me know if it is.
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila♦
8 hours ago
$begingroup$
I realize that this might be a duplicate of math.stackexchange.com/questions/7065/…, let me know if it is.
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila♦
8 hours ago
$begingroup$
I realize that this might be a duplicate of math.stackexchange.com/questions/7065/…, let me know if it is.
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila♦
8 hours ago
add a comment |
2 Answers
2
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
No, of course not. Not even in the case that $kappa=omega$, as that would be exactly countable choice which is known to be unprovable.
Moreover, even if you assume that for any ordinal $kappa$ the product of $kappa$ non-empty sets is non-empty, you still cannot prove the axiom of choice in general. In fact, you cannot even prove that every uncountable cardinal is comparable with $aleph_1$.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Does the principle in your second paragraph have a standard name?
$endgroup$
– Alex Kruckman
2 hours ago
add a comment |
$begingroup$
The transfinite induction you're probably imagining fails at every limit ordinal.
I suppose you're thinking "then take the union of the functions we have so far", but which of them? Since there are many sequences for each shorter length, in order for "take the union" to work you need to be able to point to just one of each length in a way that fits together -- but that is exactly what $alpha$-choice which you're just trying to prove is for. So this argument actually begs the question.
Even though we think of the induction as a process that happens in sequence, that's not how it works formally. In the induction step for $alpha$ all the induction hypothesis lets you assume is that there exist one or more sequences of every length shorter than $alpha$ -- you don't have a particular selection of them already singled out as "the ones we chose in previous steps". There are no "previous steps", because the induction step in transfinite induction must be proved just once but for an arbitrary $alpha$.
This may be easier to wrap your mind around if you remember how to prove transfinite induction from the fact that ordinals are well-ordered. In this proof you're not actually doing anything step by step -- it's an indirect proof where we say, once and for all, something like this:
Suppose the desired property fails for at least one ordinal. Then bla bla well-ordered bla bla, and therefore there is a smallest $alpha$ that the property fails for. Then apply the induction step just once, for that $alpha$, and conclude that the property doesn't actually fail there after all -- a contradiction.
This proof never applies the induction step to all the ordinals before the supposed first point where the property fails. So we shouldn't assume when we apply it that it "has already run", so to say, for the smaller ordinals. We just know that its conclusion is, somehow, true for each of them independently.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
Your Answer
StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);
StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});
function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});
}
});
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3283402%2fwell-ordered-cartesian-product-in-zf%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
2 Answers
2
active
oldest
votes
2 Answers
2
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
No, of course not. Not even in the case that $kappa=omega$, as that would be exactly countable choice which is known to be unprovable.
Moreover, even if you assume that for any ordinal $kappa$ the product of $kappa$ non-empty sets is non-empty, you still cannot prove the axiom of choice in general. In fact, you cannot even prove that every uncountable cardinal is comparable with $aleph_1$.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Does the principle in your second paragraph have a standard name?
$endgroup$
– Alex Kruckman
2 hours ago
add a comment |
$begingroup$
No, of course not. Not even in the case that $kappa=omega$, as that would be exactly countable choice which is known to be unprovable.
Moreover, even if you assume that for any ordinal $kappa$ the product of $kappa$ non-empty sets is non-empty, you still cannot prove the axiom of choice in general. In fact, you cannot even prove that every uncountable cardinal is comparable with $aleph_1$.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Does the principle in your second paragraph have a standard name?
$endgroup$
– Alex Kruckman
2 hours ago
add a comment |
$begingroup$
No, of course not. Not even in the case that $kappa=omega$, as that would be exactly countable choice which is known to be unprovable.
Moreover, even if you assume that for any ordinal $kappa$ the product of $kappa$ non-empty sets is non-empty, you still cannot prove the axiom of choice in general. In fact, you cannot even prove that every uncountable cardinal is comparable with $aleph_1$.
$endgroup$
No, of course not. Not even in the case that $kappa=omega$, as that would be exactly countable choice which is known to be unprovable.
Moreover, even if you assume that for any ordinal $kappa$ the product of $kappa$ non-empty sets is non-empty, you still cannot prove the axiom of choice in general. In fact, you cannot even prove that every uncountable cardinal is comparable with $aleph_1$.
answered 8 hours ago
Asaf Karagila♦Asaf Karagila
313k34 gold badges448 silver badges782 bronze badges
313k34 gold badges448 silver badges782 bronze badges
$begingroup$
Does the principle in your second paragraph have a standard name?
$endgroup$
– Alex Kruckman
2 hours ago
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Does the principle in your second paragraph have a standard name?
$endgroup$
– Alex Kruckman
2 hours ago
$begingroup$
Does the principle in your second paragraph have a standard name?
$endgroup$
– Alex Kruckman
2 hours ago
$begingroup$
Does the principle in your second paragraph have a standard name?
$endgroup$
– Alex Kruckman
2 hours ago
add a comment |
$begingroup$
The transfinite induction you're probably imagining fails at every limit ordinal.
I suppose you're thinking "then take the union of the functions we have so far", but which of them? Since there are many sequences for each shorter length, in order for "take the union" to work you need to be able to point to just one of each length in a way that fits together -- but that is exactly what $alpha$-choice which you're just trying to prove is for. So this argument actually begs the question.
Even though we think of the induction as a process that happens in sequence, that's not how it works formally. In the induction step for $alpha$ all the induction hypothesis lets you assume is that there exist one or more sequences of every length shorter than $alpha$ -- you don't have a particular selection of them already singled out as "the ones we chose in previous steps". There are no "previous steps", because the induction step in transfinite induction must be proved just once but for an arbitrary $alpha$.
This may be easier to wrap your mind around if you remember how to prove transfinite induction from the fact that ordinals are well-ordered. In this proof you're not actually doing anything step by step -- it's an indirect proof where we say, once and for all, something like this:
Suppose the desired property fails for at least one ordinal. Then bla bla well-ordered bla bla, and therefore there is a smallest $alpha$ that the property fails for. Then apply the induction step just once, for that $alpha$, and conclude that the property doesn't actually fail there after all -- a contradiction.
This proof never applies the induction step to all the ordinals before the supposed first point where the property fails. So we shouldn't assume when we apply it that it "has already run", so to say, for the smaller ordinals. We just know that its conclusion is, somehow, true for each of them independently.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
The transfinite induction you're probably imagining fails at every limit ordinal.
I suppose you're thinking "then take the union of the functions we have so far", but which of them? Since there are many sequences for each shorter length, in order for "take the union" to work you need to be able to point to just one of each length in a way that fits together -- but that is exactly what $alpha$-choice which you're just trying to prove is for. So this argument actually begs the question.
Even though we think of the induction as a process that happens in sequence, that's not how it works formally. In the induction step for $alpha$ all the induction hypothesis lets you assume is that there exist one or more sequences of every length shorter than $alpha$ -- you don't have a particular selection of them already singled out as "the ones we chose in previous steps". There are no "previous steps", because the induction step in transfinite induction must be proved just once but for an arbitrary $alpha$.
This may be easier to wrap your mind around if you remember how to prove transfinite induction from the fact that ordinals are well-ordered. In this proof you're not actually doing anything step by step -- it's an indirect proof where we say, once and for all, something like this:
Suppose the desired property fails for at least one ordinal. Then bla bla well-ordered bla bla, and therefore there is a smallest $alpha$ that the property fails for. Then apply the induction step just once, for that $alpha$, and conclude that the property doesn't actually fail there after all -- a contradiction.
This proof never applies the induction step to all the ordinals before the supposed first point where the property fails. So we shouldn't assume when we apply it that it "has already run", so to say, for the smaller ordinals. We just know that its conclusion is, somehow, true for each of them independently.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
The transfinite induction you're probably imagining fails at every limit ordinal.
I suppose you're thinking "then take the union of the functions we have so far", but which of them? Since there are many sequences for each shorter length, in order for "take the union" to work you need to be able to point to just one of each length in a way that fits together -- but that is exactly what $alpha$-choice which you're just trying to prove is for. So this argument actually begs the question.
Even though we think of the induction as a process that happens in sequence, that's not how it works formally. In the induction step for $alpha$ all the induction hypothesis lets you assume is that there exist one or more sequences of every length shorter than $alpha$ -- you don't have a particular selection of them already singled out as "the ones we chose in previous steps". There are no "previous steps", because the induction step in transfinite induction must be proved just once but for an arbitrary $alpha$.
This may be easier to wrap your mind around if you remember how to prove transfinite induction from the fact that ordinals are well-ordered. In this proof you're not actually doing anything step by step -- it's an indirect proof where we say, once and for all, something like this:
Suppose the desired property fails for at least one ordinal. Then bla bla well-ordered bla bla, and therefore there is a smallest $alpha$ that the property fails for. Then apply the induction step just once, for that $alpha$, and conclude that the property doesn't actually fail there after all -- a contradiction.
This proof never applies the induction step to all the ordinals before the supposed first point where the property fails. So we shouldn't assume when we apply it that it "has already run", so to say, for the smaller ordinals. We just know that its conclusion is, somehow, true for each of them independently.
$endgroup$
The transfinite induction you're probably imagining fails at every limit ordinal.
I suppose you're thinking "then take the union of the functions we have so far", but which of them? Since there are many sequences for each shorter length, in order for "take the union" to work you need to be able to point to just one of each length in a way that fits together -- but that is exactly what $alpha$-choice which you're just trying to prove is for. So this argument actually begs the question.
Even though we think of the induction as a process that happens in sequence, that's not how it works formally. In the induction step for $alpha$ all the induction hypothesis lets you assume is that there exist one or more sequences of every length shorter than $alpha$ -- you don't have a particular selection of them already singled out as "the ones we chose in previous steps". There are no "previous steps", because the induction step in transfinite induction must be proved just once but for an arbitrary $alpha$.
This may be easier to wrap your mind around if you remember how to prove transfinite induction from the fact that ordinals are well-ordered. In this proof you're not actually doing anything step by step -- it's an indirect proof where we say, once and for all, something like this:
Suppose the desired property fails for at least one ordinal. Then bla bla well-ordered bla bla, and therefore there is a smallest $alpha$ that the property fails for. Then apply the induction step just once, for that $alpha$, and conclude that the property doesn't actually fail there after all -- a contradiction.
This proof never applies the induction step to all the ordinals before the supposed first point where the property fails. So we shouldn't assume when we apply it that it "has already run", so to say, for the smaller ordinals. We just know that its conclusion is, somehow, true for each of them independently.
edited 8 hours ago
answered 8 hours ago
Henning MakholmHenning Makholm
251k17 gold badges329 silver badges572 bronze badges
251k17 gold badges329 silver badges572 bronze badges
add a comment |
add a comment |
Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3283402%2fwell-ordered-cartesian-product-in-zf%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
$begingroup$
I realize that this might be a duplicate of math.stackexchange.com/questions/7065/…, let me know if it is.
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila♦
8 hours ago