Understanding the implication of what “well-defined” means for the operation in quotient group ...

How to manage monthly salary

Why hard-Brexiteers don't insist on a hard border to prevent illegal immigration after Brexit?

Why is the Constellation's nose gear so long?

Did Scotland spend $250,000 for the slogan "Welcome to Scotland"?

Apparent duplicates between Haynes service instructions and MOT

Can someone be penalized for an "unlawful" act if no penalty is specified?

What is the meaning of Triage in Cybersec world?

Aging parents with no investments

Can a flute soloist sit?

One word riddle: Vowel in the middle

Identify boardgame from Big movie

How to answer pointed "are you quitting" questioning when I don't want them to suspect

Did 3000BC Egyptians use meteoric iron weapons?

What to do when moving next to a bird sanctuary with a loosely-domesticated cat?

Why didn't the Event Horizon Telescope team mention Sagittarius A*?

How are circuits which use complex ICs normally simulated?

Can one be advised by a professor who is very far away?

What is the most effective way of iterating a std::vector and why?

Origin of "cooter" meaning "vagina"

How can I autofill dates in Excel excluding Sunday?

Why do UK politicians seemingly ignore opinion polls on Brexit?

If a Druid sees an animal’s corpse, can they Wild Shape into that animal?

Does the shape of a die affect the probability of a number being rolled?

Are spiders unable to hurt humans, especially very small spiders?



Understanding the implication of what “well-defined” means for the operation in quotient group



The 2019 Stack Overflow Developer Survey Results Are InFor $Q$ the quaternion group, is $Q/Z(Q)$ a group? For which operation?Is the Axiom of Choice implicitly used when defining a binary operation on a quotient object?Why can quotient groups only be defined for subgroups?Convincing normal subgroup proof?Coset multiplication giving a well defined binary operationShow that the group operation is well definedWhat does well-defined mean? In general or in this context (quotient group)Quotient group is well-definedClosed under an operation which is not well-defined?Showing quotient group operations are well defined












3












$begingroup$


I want to get an intuitive idea of the operation being "well-defined" for quotient groups. So, let's say I have a group $G$, with subgroup $H$, and let's say my set of left cosets is $G/K$. My lecture note says this: If $H$ is normal, then $G/H$ is a group under binary operation $aH circ bH = (ab)H$. So let's say I am asked whether $G/H$ forms a group where $H$ is not normal, and I have already determined that. My professor referred to the following which I am not sure if I totally understand:



Show that there are $a, b, a', b' in G$ such that $ aH = a'H$ and $bH = b'H$ but $aH circ bH = (ab)H neq a'H circ b'H = (a'b')H$, and you are done, and I did what she suggested, but I am not sure what is going on. So,



$1.$ What did I exactly show by proving what my professor suggested?



$2.$ In general, is it a strategy that every time you have to prove $G/H$ does not form a group for a non-normal $H$, you show that the operation is not well-defined?



Also, a quick google search also showed me that the theorem that talks about $G/K$ forming a group is an "if and only if" statement and not difficult to prove as well. Still, any help on my questions above would be great.










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$








  • 6




    $begingroup$
    For multiplication of cosets to be well-defined you have to get the same answer no matter which representative of the cosets you choose
    $endgroup$
    – J. W. Tanner
    yesterday








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    If $C,D$ are cosets of $H$, we'd like to define $C*D$ by taking a random element of $a in C$ and a random element of $b in D$ and define $C*D = E$ where $E$ is the coset containing $ab$. But we've made a random choice here, so we would expect $E$ to also be "random". But as it turns out, we get the same result $E$ no matter what $a, b$ we pick. That's what we mean when we say the operation is well-defined. In general, to prove something is well-defined means to prove that the "random" choices we made during the construction don't change the result.
    $endgroup$
    – Jair Taylor
    yesterday
















3












$begingroup$


I want to get an intuitive idea of the operation being "well-defined" for quotient groups. So, let's say I have a group $G$, with subgroup $H$, and let's say my set of left cosets is $G/K$. My lecture note says this: If $H$ is normal, then $G/H$ is a group under binary operation $aH circ bH = (ab)H$. So let's say I am asked whether $G/H$ forms a group where $H$ is not normal, and I have already determined that. My professor referred to the following which I am not sure if I totally understand:



Show that there are $a, b, a', b' in G$ such that $ aH = a'H$ and $bH = b'H$ but $aH circ bH = (ab)H neq a'H circ b'H = (a'b')H$, and you are done, and I did what she suggested, but I am not sure what is going on. So,



$1.$ What did I exactly show by proving what my professor suggested?



$2.$ In general, is it a strategy that every time you have to prove $G/H$ does not form a group for a non-normal $H$, you show that the operation is not well-defined?



Also, a quick google search also showed me that the theorem that talks about $G/K$ forming a group is an "if and only if" statement and not difficult to prove as well. Still, any help on my questions above would be great.










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$








  • 6




    $begingroup$
    For multiplication of cosets to be well-defined you have to get the same answer no matter which representative of the cosets you choose
    $endgroup$
    – J. W. Tanner
    yesterday








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    If $C,D$ are cosets of $H$, we'd like to define $C*D$ by taking a random element of $a in C$ and a random element of $b in D$ and define $C*D = E$ where $E$ is the coset containing $ab$. But we've made a random choice here, so we would expect $E$ to also be "random". But as it turns out, we get the same result $E$ no matter what $a, b$ we pick. That's what we mean when we say the operation is well-defined. In general, to prove something is well-defined means to prove that the "random" choices we made during the construction don't change the result.
    $endgroup$
    – Jair Taylor
    yesterday














3












3








3





$begingroup$


I want to get an intuitive idea of the operation being "well-defined" for quotient groups. So, let's say I have a group $G$, with subgroup $H$, and let's say my set of left cosets is $G/K$. My lecture note says this: If $H$ is normal, then $G/H$ is a group under binary operation $aH circ bH = (ab)H$. So let's say I am asked whether $G/H$ forms a group where $H$ is not normal, and I have already determined that. My professor referred to the following which I am not sure if I totally understand:



Show that there are $a, b, a', b' in G$ such that $ aH = a'H$ and $bH = b'H$ but $aH circ bH = (ab)H neq a'H circ b'H = (a'b')H$, and you are done, and I did what she suggested, but I am not sure what is going on. So,



$1.$ What did I exactly show by proving what my professor suggested?



$2.$ In general, is it a strategy that every time you have to prove $G/H$ does not form a group for a non-normal $H$, you show that the operation is not well-defined?



Also, a quick google search also showed me that the theorem that talks about $G/K$ forming a group is an "if and only if" statement and not difficult to prove as well. Still, any help on my questions above would be great.










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$




I want to get an intuitive idea of the operation being "well-defined" for quotient groups. So, let's say I have a group $G$, with subgroup $H$, and let's say my set of left cosets is $G/K$. My lecture note says this: If $H$ is normal, then $G/H$ is a group under binary operation $aH circ bH = (ab)H$. So let's say I am asked whether $G/H$ forms a group where $H$ is not normal, and I have already determined that. My professor referred to the following which I am not sure if I totally understand:



Show that there are $a, b, a', b' in G$ such that $ aH = a'H$ and $bH = b'H$ but $aH circ bH = (ab)H neq a'H circ b'H = (a'b')H$, and you are done, and I did what she suggested, but I am not sure what is going on. So,



$1.$ What did I exactly show by proving what my professor suggested?



$2.$ In general, is it a strategy that every time you have to prove $G/H$ does not form a group for a non-normal $H$, you show that the operation is not well-defined?



Also, a quick google search also showed me that the theorem that talks about $G/K$ forming a group is an "if and only if" statement and not difficult to prove as well. Still, any help on my questions above would be great.







abstract-algebra group-theory






share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question











share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question










asked yesterday









UfomammutUfomammut

386314




386314








  • 6




    $begingroup$
    For multiplication of cosets to be well-defined you have to get the same answer no matter which representative of the cosets you choose
    $endgroup$
    – J. W. Tanner
    yesterday








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    If $C,D$ are cosets of $H$, we'd like to define $C*D$ by taking a random element of $a in C$ and a random element of $b in D$ and define $C*D = E$ where $E$ is the coset containing $ab$. But we've made a random choice here, so we would expect $E$ to also be "random". But as it turns out, we get the same result $E$ no matter what $a, b$ we pick. That's what we mean when we say the operation is well-defined. In general, to prove something is well-defined means to prove that the "random" choices we made during the construction don't change the result.
    $endgroup$
    – Jair Taylor
    yesterday














  • 6




    $begingroup$
    For multiplication of cosets to be well-defined you have to get the same answer no matter which representative of the cosets you choose
    $endgroup$
    – J. W. Tanner
    yesterday








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    If $C,D$ are cosets of $H$, we'd like to define $C*D$ by taking a random element of $a in C$ and a random element of $b in D$ and define $C*D = E$ where $E$ is the coset containing $ab$. But we've made a random choice here, so we would expect $E$ to also be "random". But as it turns out, we get the same result $E$ no matter what $a, b$ we pick. That's what we mean when we say the operation is well-defined. In general, to prove something is well-defined means to prove that the "random" choices we made during the construction don't change the result.
    $endgroup$
    – Jair Taylor
    yesterday








6




6




$begingroup$
For multiplication of cosets to be well-defined you have to get the same answer no matter which representative of the cosets you choose
$endgroup$
– J. W. Tanner
yesterday






$begingroup$
For multiplication of cosets to be well-defined you have to get the same answer no matter which representative of the cosets you choose
$endgroup$
– J. W. Tanner
yesterday






1




1




$begingroup$
If $C,D$ are cosets of $H$, we'd like to define $C*D$ by taking a random element of $a in C$ and a random element of $b in D$ and define $C*D = E$ where $E$ is the coset containing $ab$. But we've made a random choice here, so we would expect $E$ to also be "random". But as it turns out, we get the same result $E$ no matter what $a, b$ we pick. That's what we mean when we say the operation is well-defined. In general, to prove something is well-defined means to prove that the "random" choices we made during the construction don't change the result.
$endgroup$
– Jair Taylor
yesterday




$begingroup$
If $C,D$ are cosets of $H$, we'd like to define $C*D$ by taking a random element of $a in C$ and a random element of $b in D$ and define $C*D = E$ where $E$ is the coset containing $ab$. But we've made a random choice here, so we would expect $E$ to also be "random". But as it turns out, we get the same result $E$ no matter what $a, b$ we pick. That's what we mean when we say the operation is well-defined. In general, to prove something is well-defined means to prove that the "random" choices we made during the construction don't change the result.
$endgroup$
– Jair Taylor
yesterday










3 Answers
3






active

oldest

votes


















9












$begingroup$

In general, mathematicians use the phrase "well defined" when a definition is written in a form that depends (or, rather, seems to depend) on some more or less arbitrary choice. If you make such a definition, you are obligated to show that another choice that satisfied appropriate conditions would lead to the same result.



In a group the product $abc$ is well defined to be $(ab)c$ because its value does not depend on your choice of where to put the parentheses: associativity guarantees $(ab)c = a(bc)$. This fact is so intuitively clear that it's often not made explicit in a beginning algebra course.



When considering quotient groups, you want to define the multiplication of two cosets by choosing an element from each, multiplying them together, and taking the coset of the product. This coset product will be well defined only when the coset of the product of the two group elements does not depend on which ones you happened to choose. The sum of any two odd numbers will be even, so the product of cosets
$(2mathbb{Z} + 1) circ (2mathbb{Z} + 1)$ is $2mathbb{Z}$.



There is an alternative definition. You can define the product of two cosets $A$ and $B$ as
$$
A circ B = { ab | a in A text{ and } b in B }.
$$

This definition does not make any arbitrary choices, but you don't know that the set so defined is really a coset until you prove it.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    I do not know if what I am asking makes sense, but is the way the binary operation between two sets of the set of cosets is defined always the same? Also, getting back to my question, is this equivalent to proving closure under the binary operation?
    $endgroup$
    – Ufomammut
    yesterday






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Closure is a bit of a red herring. In your definition of the coset product you always get a coset as the result. The issue is proving that the particular coset is independent of the choices. In my alternative definition you have to prove that a particular set is a coset. Closure only comes up when you already have an operation defined and you want to show you don't leave some subset. So the set of odd integers is not closed under addition.
    $endgroup$
    – Ethan Bolker
    yesterday



















7












$begingroup$

Perhaps a concrete example will make it clearer?



We need a non-abelian group. Let's take the simplest one there is, namely $G=S_3$.



We need a non-normal subgroup. Let's take $H={e,(12)}$.



We need two cosets. Using $H$ itself might be too trivial, so it seems most promising to take
$$ a=(23) qquad aH = {(23),(132)} = a'H qquad a'=(132) $$
$$ b=(13) qquad bH = {(13),(123)} = b'H qquad b'=(123) $$



Now, if we had a quotient group what should the product ${(23),(132)}circ{(13),(123)}$ be?



From one perspective we have
$$(23)Hcirc(13)H =^? (123)H$$
But we could also say
$$(132)Hcirc(123)H =^? eH = H$$



But the product of the coset ${(12),(132)}$ with the coset ${(23),(123)}$ cannot be allowed to depend on what we choose to call those cosets. And here we have two calculations that say it should be two different things! So we're in trouble.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    The example helped a lot. Great explanation.
    $endgroup$
    – Ufomammut
    yesterday



















0












$begingroup$

Here's a different description that gives a different lens on all of this.



An equivalence relation on a set is a binary relation (call it $sim$) that is reflexive ($xsim x$), symmetric ($xsim yimplies ysim x$), and transitive ($xsim y land ysim z implies xsim z$). Given a group $G$ with a subgroup $H$, we can define an equivalence relation on the underlying set of $G$ via $asim b iff ab^{-1}in H$. Prove that this is indeed an equivalence relation.



An equivalence class of an element $x$ with respect to some equivalence relation $sim$ is the set ${ymid xsim y}$. I'll use $[x]$ as notation for the equivalence class of $x$ (where the relevant equivalence relation is left implicit and resolved from context). For the equivalence relation above on $G$, what does $[g]$ look like for an arbitrary element of $G$? One particularly notable case is $[1]={gmid 1sim g}={gmid g^{-1}in H}=H$.



Since our example is on a group, it would be nice to know that the equivalence relation respects the group operation. The idea is that we want to think of $xsim y$ as $x$ "equals" $y$, and so if $xsim x'$ and $ysim y'$ we would want $xysim x'y'$ as would obviously be the case for equality. (Show that this is the same as $[x][y]=[xy]$ where the multiplication of two sets of group elements is defined as $XY={xymid xin Xland yin Y}$.) An equivalence that respects the group operation is called a congruence. (More generally, a congruence refers to an equivalence relation that respects whatever operations are relevant. For example, a congruence on rings would respect multiplication and addition.) Alternatively, if we're given an equivalence relation, we can say that an operation is well-defined if it takes "equals" to "equals". In other words, "the group operation is well-defined with respect to $sim$" is the same as "$sim$ respects the group operation". The only difference is one of connotation, namely which of the group operation or the equivalence relation we would "blame" if the statement failed to hold.



So the first question is: is the equivalence defined above a congruence?



Given any equivalence relation on a group, we can extend it to a congruence. That is, we can consider the smallest congruence that contains the original equivalence relation. This is called the congruence generated by the equivalence relation. It's quite possible that the generated congruence is the same as the original equivalence relation. Now let's assume we've been given a congruence on $G$ written $approx$. We have $aapprox biff ab^{-1}approx 1$. (Why?) We can thus show $aapprox biff ab^{-1}in[1]$, mimicking our first equivalence relation.



Second and third questions: What does $[1]$ look like in this case? What does $[1]$ look like for the congruence generated by our first equivalence relation, $sim$?






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$














    Your Answer





    StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
    return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
    StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
    StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
    });
    });
    }, "mathjax-editing");

    StackExchange.ready(function() {
    var channelOptions = {
    tags: "".split(" "),
    id: "69"
    };
    initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

    StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
    // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
    if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
    StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
    createEditor();
    });
    }
    else {
    createEditor();
    }
    });

    function createEditor() {
    StackExchange.prepareEditor({
    heartbeatType: 'answer',
    autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
    convertImagesToLinks: true,
    noModals: true,
    showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
    reputationToPostImages: 10,
    bindNavPrevention: true,
    postfix: "",
    imageUploader: {
    brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
    contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
    allowUrls: true
    },
    noCode: true, onDemand: true,
    discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
    ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
    });


    }
    });














    draft saved

    draft discarded


















    StackExchange.ready(
    function () {
    StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3181739%2funderstanding-the-implication-of-what-well-defined-means-for-the-operation-in%23new-answer', 'question_page');
    }
    );

    Post as a guest















    Required, but never shown

























    3 Answers
    3






    active

    oldest

    votes








    3 Answers
    3






    active

    oldest

    votes









    active

    oldest

    votes






    active

    oldest

    votes









    9












    $begingroup$

    In general, mathematicians use the phrase "well defined" when a definition is written in a form that depends (or, rather, seems to depend) on some more or less arbitrary choice. If you make such a definition, you are obligated to show that another choice that satisfied appropriate conditions would lead to the same result.



    In a group the product $abc$ is well defined to be $(ab)c$ because its value does not depend on your choice of where to put the parentheses: associativity guarantees $(ab)c = a(bc)$. This fact is so intuitively clear that it's often not made explicit in a beginning algebra course.



    When considering quotient groups, you want to define the multiplication of two cosets by choosing an element from each, multiplying them together, and taking the coset of the product. This coset product will be well defined only when the coset of the product of the two group elements does not depend on which ones you happened to choose. The sum of any two odd numbers will be even, so the product of cosets
    $(2mathbb{Z} + 1) circ (2mathbb{Z} + 1)$ is $2mathbb{Z}$.



    There is an alternative definition. You can define the product of two cosets $A$ and $B$ as
    $$
    A circ B = { ab | a in A text{ and } b in B }.
    $$

    This definition does not make any arbitrary choices, but you don't know that the set so defined is really a coset until you prove it.






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$













    • $begingroup$
      I do not know if what I am asking makes sense, but is the way the binary operation between two sets of the set of cosets is defined always the same? Also, getting back to my question, is this equivalent to proving closure under the binary operation?
      $endgroup$
      – Ufomammut
      yesterday






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      Closure is a bit of a red herring. In your definition of the coset product you always get a coset as the result. The issue is proving that the particular coset is independent of the choices. In my alternative definition you have to prove that a particular set is a coset. Closure only comes up when you already have an operation defined and you want to show you don't leave some subset. So the set of odd integers is not closed under addition.
      $endgroup$
      – Ethan Bolker
      yesterday
















    9












    $begingroup$

    In general, mathematicians use the phrase "well defined" when a definition is written in a form that depends (or, rather, seems to depend) on some more or less arbitrary choice. If you make such a definition, you are obligated to show that another choice that satisfied appropriate conditions would lead to the same result.



    In a group the product $abc$ is well defined to be $(ab)c$ because its value does not depend on your choice of where to put the parentheses: associativity guarantees $(ab)c = a(bc)$. This fact is so intuitively clear that it's often not made explicit in a beginning algebra course.



    When considering quotient groups, you want to define the multiplication of two cosets by choosing an element from each, multiplying them together, and taking the coset of the product. This coset product will be well defined only when the coset of the product of the two group elements does not depend on which ones you happened to choose. The sum of any two odd numbers will be even, so the product of cosets
    $(2mathbb{Z} + 1) circ (2mathbb{Z} + 1)$ is $2mathbb{Z}$.



    There is an alternative definition. You can define the product of two cosets $A$ and $B$ as
    $$
    A circ B = { ab | a in A text{ and } b in B }.
    $$

    This definition does not make any arbitrary choices, but you don't know that the set so defined is really a coset until you prove it.






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$













    • $begingroup$
      I do not know if what I am asking makes sense, but is the way the binary operation between two sets of the set of cosets is defined always the same? Also, getting back to my question, is this equivalent to proving closure under the binary operation?
      $endgroup$
      – Ufomammut
      yesterday






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      Closure is a bit of a red herring. In your definition of the coset product you always get a coset as the result. The issue is proving that the particular coset is independent of the choices. In my alternative definition you have to prove that a particular set is a coset. Closure only comes up when you already have an operation defined and you want to show you don't leave some subset. So the set of odd integers is not closed under addition.
      $endgroup$
      – Ethan Bolker
      yesterday














    9












    9








    9





    $begingroup$

    In general, mathematicians use the phrase "well defined" when a definition is written in a form that depends (or, rather, seems to depend) on some more or less arbitrary choice. If you make such a definition, you are obligated to show that another choice that satisfied appropriate conditions would lead to the same result.



    In a group the product $abc$ is well defined to be $(ab)c$ because its value does not depend on your choice of where to put the parentheses: associativity guarantees $(ab)c = a(bc)$. This fact is so intuitively clear that it's often not made explicit in a beginning algebra course.



    When considering quotient groups, you want to define the multiplication of two cosets by choosing an element from each, multiplying them together, and taking the coset of the product. This coset product will be well defined only when the coset of the product of the two group elements does not depend on which ones you happened to choose. The sum of any two odd numbers will be even, so the product of cosets
    $(2mathbb{Z} + 1) circ (2mathbb{Z} + 1)$ is $2mathbb{Z}$.



    There is an alternative definition. You can define the product of two cosets $A$ and $B$ as
    $$
    A circ B = { ab | a in A text{ and } b in B }.
    $$

    This definition does not make any arbitrary choices, but you don't know that the set so defined is really a coset until you prove it.






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$



    In general, mathematicians use the phrase "well defined" when a definition is written in a form that depends (or, rather, seems to depend) on some more or less arbitrary choice. If you make such a definition, you are obligated to show that another choice that satisfied appropriate conditions would lead to the same result.



    In a group the product $abc$ is well defined to be $(ab)c$ because its value does not depend on your choice of where to put the parentheses: associativity guarantees $(ab)c = a(bc)$. This fact is so intuitively clear that it's often not made explicit in a beginning algebra course.



    When considering quotient groups, you want to define the multiplication of two cosets by choosing an element from each, multiplying them together, and taking the coset of the product. This coset product will be well defined only when the coset of the product of the two group elements does not depend on which ones you happened to choose. The sum of any two odd numbers will be even, so the product of cosets
    $(2mathbb{Z} + 1) circ (2mathbb{Z} + 1)$ is $2mathbb{Z}$.



    There is an alternative definition. You can define the product of two cosets $A$ and $B$ as
    $$
    A circ B = { ab | a in A text{ and } b in B }.
    $$

    This definition does not make any arbitrary choices, but you don't know that the set so defined is really a coset until you prove it.







    share|cite|improve this answer














    share|cite|improve this answer



    share|cite|improve this answer








    edited yesterday

























    answered yesterday









    Ethan BolkerEthan Bolker

    46k553120




    46k553120












    • $begingroup$
      I do not know if what I am asking makes sense, but is the way the binary operation between two sets of the set of cosets is defined always the same? Also, getting back to my question, is this equivalent to proving closure under the binary operation?
      $endgroup$
      – Ufomammut
      yesterday






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      Closure is a bit of a red herring. In your definition of the coset product you always get a coset as the result. The issue is proving that the particular coset is independent of the choices. In my alternative definition you have to prove that a particular set is a coset. Closure only comes up when you already have an operation defined and you want to show you don't leave some subset. So the set of odd integers is not closed under addition.
      $endgroup$
      – Ethan Bolker
      yesterday


















    • $begingroup$
      I do not know if what I am asking makes sense, but is the way the binary operation between two sets of the set of cosets is defined always the same? Also, getting back to my question, is this equivalent to proving closure under the binary operation?
      $endgroup$
      – Ufomammut
      yesterday






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      Closure is a bit of a red herring. In your definition of the coset product you always get a coset as the result. The issue is proving that the particular coset is independent of the choices. In my alternative definition you have to prove that a particular set is a coset. Closure only comes up when you already have an operation defined and you want to show you don't leave some subset. So the set of odd integers is not closed under addition.
      $endgroup$
      – Ethan Bolker
      yesterday
















    $begingroup$
    I do not know if what I am asking makes sense, but is the way the binary operation between two sets of the set of cosets is defined always the same? Also, getting back to my question, is this equivalent to proving closure under the binary operation?
    $endgroup$
    – Ufomammut
    yesterday




    $begingroup$
    I do not know if what I am asking makes sense, but is the way the binary operation between two sets of the set of cosets is defined always the same? Also, getting back to my question, is this equivalent to proving closure under the binary operation?
    $endgroup$
    – Ufomammut
    yesterday




    1




    1




    $begingroup$
    Closure is a bit of a red herring. In your definition of the coset product you always get a coset as the result. The issue is proving that the particular coset is independent of the choices. In my alternative definition you have to prove that a particular set is a coset. Closure only comes up when you already have an operation defined and you want to show you don't leave some subset. So the set of odd integers is not closed under addition.
    $endgroup$
    – Ethan Bolker
    yesterday




    $begingroup$
    Closure is a bit of a red herring. In your definition of the coset product you always get a coset as the result. The issue is proving that the particular coset is independent of the choices. In my alternative definition you have to prove that a particular set is a coset. Closure only comes up when you already have an operation defined and you want to show you don't leave some subset. So the set of odd integers is not closed under addition.
    $endgroup$
    – Ethan Bolker
    yesterday











    7












    $begingroup$

    Perhaps a concrete example will make it clearer?



    We need a non-abelian group. Let's take the simplest one there is, namely $G=S_3$.



    We need a non-normal subgroup. Let's take $H={e,(12)}$.



    We need two cosets. Using $H$ itself might be too trivial, so it seems most promising to take
    $$ a=(23) qquad aH = {(23),(132)} = a'H qquad a'=(132) $$
    $$ b=(13) qquad bH = {(13),(123)} = b'H qquad b'=(123) $$



    Now, if we had a quotient group what should the product ${(23),(132)}circ{(13),(123)}$ be?



    From one perspective we have
    $$(23)Hcirc(13)H =^? (123)H$$
    But we could also say
    $$(132)Hcirc(123)H =^? eH = H$$



    But the product of the coset ${(12),(132)}$ with the coset ${(23),(123)}$ cannot be allowed to depend on what we choose to call those cosets. And here we have two calculations that say it should be two different things! So we're in trouble.






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$













    • $begingroup$
      The example helped a lot. Great explanation.
      $endgroup$
      – Ufomammut
      yesterday
















    7












    $begingroup$

    Perhaps a concrete example will make it clearer?



    We need a non-abelian group. Let's take the simplest one there is, namely $G=S_3$.



    We need a non-normal subgroup. Let's take $H={e,(12)}$.



    We need two cosets. Using $H$ itself might be too trivial, so it seems most promising to take
    $$ a=(23) qquad aH = {(23),(132)} = a'H qquad a'=(132) $$
    $$ b=(13) qquad bH = {(13),(123)} = b'H qquad b'=(123) $$



    Now, if we had a quotient group what should the product ${(23),(132)}circ{(13),(123)}$ be?



    From one perspective we have
    $$(23)Hcirc(13)H =^? (123)H$$
    But we could also say
    $$(132)Hcirc(123)H =^? eH = H$$



    But the product of the coset ${(12),(132)}$ with the coset ${(23),(123)}$ cannot be allowed to depend on what we choose to call those cosets. And here we have two calculations that say it should be two different things! So we're in trouble.






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$













    • $begingroup$
      The example helped a lot. Great explanation.
      $endgroup$
      – Ufomammut
      yesterday














    7












    7








    7





    $begingroup$

    Perhaps a concrete example will make it clearer?



    We need a non-abelian group. Let's take the simplest one there is, namely $G=S_3$.



    We need a non-normal subgroup. Let's take $H={e,(12)}$.



    We need two cosets. Using $H$ itself might be too trivial, so it seems most promising to take
    $$ a=(23) qquad aH = {(23),(132)} = a'H qquad a'=(132) $$
    $$ b=(13) qquad bH = {(13),(123)} = b'H qquad b'=(123) $$



    Now, if we had a quotient group what should the product ${(23),(132)}circ{(13),(123)}$ be?



    From one perspective we have
    $$(23)Hcirc(13)H =^? (123)H$$
    But we could also say
    $$(132)Hcirc(123)H =^? eH = H$$



    But the product of the coset ${(12),(132)}$ with the coset ${(23),(123)}$ cannot be allowed to depend on what we choose to call those cosets. And here we have two calculations that say it should be two different things! So we're in trouble.






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$



    Perhaps a concrete example will make it clearer?



    We need a non-abelian group. Let's take the simplest one there is, namely $G=S_3$.



    We need a non-normal subgroup. Let's take $H={e,(12)}$.



    We need two cosets. Using $H$ itself might be too trivial, so it seems most promising to take
    $$ a=(23) qquad aH = {(23),(132)} = a'H qquad a'=(132) $$
    $$ b=(13) qquad bH = {(13),(123)} = b'H qquad b'=(123) $$



    Now, if we had a quotient group what should the product ${(23),(132)}circ{(13),(123)}$ be?



    From one perspective we have
    $$(23)Hcirc(13)H =^? (123)H$$
    But we could also say
    $$(132)Hcirc(123)H =^? eH = H$$



    But the product of the coset ${(12),(132)}$ with the coset ${(23),(123)}$ cannot be allowed to depend on what we choose to call those cosets. And here we have two calculations that say it should be two different things! So we're in trouble.







    share|cite|improve this answer














    share|cite|improve this answer



    share|cite|improve this answer








    edited 17 hours ago

























    answered yesterday









    Henning MakholmHenning Makholm

    243k17310554




    243k17310554












    • $begingroup$
      The example helped a lot. Great explanation.
      $endgroup$
      – Ufomammut
      yesterday


















    • $begingroup$
      The example helped a lot. Great explanation.
      $endgroup$
      – Ufomammut
      yesterday
















    $begingroup$
    The example helped a lot. Great explanation.
    $endgroup$
    – Ufomammut
    yesterday




    $begingroup$
    The example helped a lot. Great explanation.
    $endgroup$
    – Ufomammut
    yesterday











    0












    $begingroup$

    Here's a different description that gives a different lens on all of this.



    An equivalence relation on a set is a binary relation (call it $sim$) that is reflexive ($xsim x$), symmetric ($xsim yimplies ysim x$), and transitive ($xsim y land ysim z implies xsim z$). Given a group $G$ with a subgroup $H$, we can define an equivalence relation on the underlying set of $G$ via $asim b iff ab^{-1}in H$. Prove that this is indeed an equivalence relation.



    An equivalence class of an element $x$ with respect to some equivalence relation $sim$ is the set ${ymid xsim y}$. I'll use $[x]$ as notation for the equivalence class of $x$ (where the relevant equivalence relation is left implicit and resolved from context). For the equivalence relation above on $G$, what does $[g]$ look like for an arbitrary element of $G$? One particularly notable case is $[1]={gmid 1sim g}={gmid g^{-1}in H}=H$.



    Since our example is on a group, it would be nice to know that the equivalence relation respects the group operation. The idea is that we want to think of $xsim y$ as $x$ "equals" $y$, and so if $xsim x'$ and $ysim y'$ we would want $xysim x'y'$ as would obviously be the case for equality. (Show that this is the same as $[x][y]=[xy]$ where the multiplication of two sets of group elements is defined as $XY={xymid xin Xland yin Y}$.) An equivalence that respects the group operation is called a congruence. (More generally, a congruence refers to an equivalence relation that respects whatever operations are relevant. For example, a congruence on rings would respect multiplication and addition.) Alternatively, if we're given an equivalence relation, we can say that an operation is well-defined if it takes "equals" to "equals". In other words, "the group operation is well-defined with respect to $sim$" is the same as "$sim$ respects the group operation". The only difference is one of connotation, namely which of the group operation or the equivalence relation we would "blame" if the statement failed to hold.



    So the first question is: is the equivalence defined above a congruence?



    Given any equivalence relation on a group, we can extend it to a congruence. That is, we can consider the smallest congruence that contains the original equivalence relation. This is called the congruence generated by the equivalence relation. It's quite possible that the generated congruence is the same as the original equivalence relation. Now let's assume we've been given a congruence on $G$ written $approx$. We have $aapprox biff ab^{-1}approx 1$. (Why?) We can thus show $aapprox biff ab^{-1}in[1]$, mimicking our first equivalence relation.



    Second and third questions: What does $[1]$ look like in this case? What does $[1]$ look like for the congruence generated by our first equivalence relation, $sim$?






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$


















      0












      $begingroup$

      Here's a different description that gives a different lens on all of this.



      An equivalence relation on a set is a binary relation (call it $sim$) that is reflexive ($xsim x$), symmetric ($xsim yimplies ysim x$), and transitive ($xsim y land ysim z implies xsim z$). Given a group $G$ with a subgroup $H$, we can define an equivalence relation on the underlying set of $G$ via $asim b iff ab^{-1}in H$. Prove that this is indeed an equivalence relation.



      An equivalence class of an element $x$ with respect to some equivalence relation $sim$ is the set ${ymid xsim y}$. I'll use $[x]$ as notation for the equivalence class of $x$ (where the relevant equivalence relation is left implicit and resolved from context). For the equivalence relation above on $G$, what does $[g]$ look like for an arbitrary element of $G$? One particularly notable case is $[1]={gmid 1sim g}={gmid g^{-1}in H}=H$.



      Since our example is on a group, it would be nice to know that the equivalence relation respects the group operation. The idea is that we want to think of $xsim y$ as $x$ "equals" $y$, and so if $xsim x'$ and $ysim y'$ we would want $xysim x'y'$ as would obviously be the case for equality. (Show that this is the same as $[x][y]=[xy]$ where the multiplication of two sets of group elements is defined as $XY={xymid xin Xland yin Y}$.) An equivalence that respects the group operation is called a congruence. (More generally, a congruence refers to an equivalence relation that respects whatever operations are relevant. For example, a congruence on rings would respect multiplication and addition.) Alternatively, if we're given an equivalence relation, we can say that an operation is well-defined if it takes "equals" to "equals". In other words, "the group operation is well-defined with respect to $sim$" is the same as "$sim$ respects the group operation". The only difference is one of connotation, namely which of the group operation or the equivalence relation we would "blame" if the statement failed to hold.



      So the first question is: is the equivalence defined above a congruence?



      Given any equivalence relation on a group, we can extend it to a congruence. That is, we can consider the smallest congruence that contains the original equivalence relation. This is called the congruence generated by the equivalence relation. It's quite possible that the generated congruence is the same as the original equivalence relation. Now let's assume we've been given a congruence on $G$ written $approx$. We have $aapprox biff ab^{-1}approx 1$. (Why?) We can thus show $aapprox biff ab^{-1}in[1]$, mimicking our first equivalence relation.



      Second and third questions: What does $[1]$ look like in this case? What does $[1]$ look like for the congruence generated by our first equivalence relation, $sim$?






      share|cite|improve this answer









      $endgroup$
















        0












        0








        0





        $begingroup$

        Here's a different description that gives a different lens on all of this.



        An equivalence relation on a set is a binary relation (call it $sim$) that is reflexive ($xsim x$), symmetric ($xsim yimplies ysim x$), and transitive ($xsim y land ysim z implies xsim z$). Given a group $G$ with a subgroup $H$, we can define an equivalence relation on the underlying set of $G$ via $asim b iff ab^{-1}in H$. Prove that this is indeed an equivalence relation.



        An equivalence class of an element $x$ with respect to some equivalence relation $sim$ is the set ${ymid xsim y}$. I'll use $[x]$ as notation for the equivalence class of $x$ (where the relevant equivalence relation is left implicit and resolved from context). For the equivalence relation above on $G$, what does $[g]$ look like for an arbitrary element of $G$? One particularly notable case is $[1]={gmid 1sim g}={gmid g^{-1}in H}=H$.



        Since our example is on a group, it would be nice to know that the equivalence relation respects the group operation. The idea is that we want to think of $xsim y$ as $x$ "equals" $y$, and so if $xsim x'$ and $ysim y'$ we would want $xysim x'y'$ as would obviously be the case for equality. (Show that this is the same as $[x][y]=[xy]$ where the multiplication of two sets of group elements is defined as $XY={xymid xin Xland yin Y}$.) An equivalence that respects the group operation is called a congruence. (More generally, a congruence refers to an equivalence relation that respects whatever operations are relevant. For example, a congruence on rings would respect multiplication and addition.) Alternatively, if we're given an equivalence relation, we can say that an operation is well-defined if it takes "equals" to "equals". In other words, "the group operation is well-defined with respect to $sim$" is the same as "$sim$ respects the group operation". The only difference is one of connotation, namely which of the group operation or the equivalence relation we would "blame" if the statement failed to hold.



        So the first question is: is the equivalence defined above a congruence?



        Given any equivalence relation on a group, we can extend it to a congruence. That is, we can consider the smallest congruence that contains the original equivalence relation. This is called the congruence generated by the equivalence relation. It's quite possible that the generated congruence is the same as the original equivalence relation. Now let's assume we've been given a congruence on $G$ written $approx$. We have $aapprox biff ab^{-1}approx 1$. (Why?) We can thus show $aapprox biff ab^{-1}in[1]$, mimicking our first equivalence relation.



        Second and third questions: What does $[1]$ look like in this case? What does $[1]$ look like for the congruence generated by our first equivalence relation, $sim$?






        share|cite|improve this answer









        $endgroup$



        Here's a different description that gives a different lens on all of this.



        An equivalence relation on a set is a binary relation (call it $sim$) that is reflexive ($xsim x$), symmetric ($xsim yimplies ysim x$), and transitive ($xsim y land ysim z implies xsim z$). Given a group $G$ with a subgroup $H$, we can define an equivalence relation on the underlying set of $G$ via $asim b iff ab^{-1}in H$. Prove that this is indeed an equivalence relation.



        An equivalence class of an element $x$ with respect to some equivalence relation $sim$ is the set ${ymid xsim y}$. I'll use $[x]$ as notation for the equivalence class of $x$ (where the relevant equivalence relation is left implicit and resolved from context). For the equivalence relation above on $G$, what does $[g]$ look like for an arbitrary element of $G$? One particularly notable case is $[1]={gmid 1sim g}={gmid g^{-1}in H}=H$.



        Since our example is on a group, it would be nice to know that the equivalence relation respects the group operation. The idea is that we want to think of $xsim y$ as $x$ "equals" $y$, and so if $xsim x'$ and $ysim y'$ we would want $xysim x'y'$ as would obviously be the case for equality. (Show that this is the same as $[x][y]=[xy]$ where the multiplication of two sets of group elements is defined as $XY={xymid xin Xland yin Y}$.) An equivalence that respects the group operation is called a congruence. (More generally, a congruence refers to an equivalence relation that respects whatever operations are relevant. For example, a congruence on rings would respect multiplication and addition.) Alternatively, if we're given an equivalence relation, we can say that an operation is well-defined if it takes "equals" to "equals". In other words, "the group operation is well-defined with respect to $sim$" is the same as "$sim$ respects the group operation". The only difference is one of connotation, namely which of the group operation or the equivalence relation we would "blame" if the statement failed to hold.



        So the first question is: is the equivalence defined above a congruence?



        Given any equivalence relation on a group, we can extend it to a congruence. That is, we can consider the smallest congruence that contains the original equivalence relation. This is called the congruence generated by the equivalence relation. It's quite possible that the generated congruence is the same as the original equivalence relation. Now let's assume we've been given a congruence on $G$ written $approx$. We have $aapprox biff ab^{-1}approx 1$. (Why?) We can thus show $aapprox biff ab^{-1}in[1]$, mimicking our first equivalence relation.



        Second and third questions: What does $[1]$ look like in this case? What does $[1]$ look like for the congruence generated by our first equivalence relation, $sim$?







        share|cite|improve this answer












        share|cite|improve this answer



        share|cite|improve this answer










        answered 8 hours ago









        Derek ElkinsDerek Elkins

        17.6k11437




        17.6k11437






























            draft saved

            draft discarded




















































            Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


            • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

            But avoid



            • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

            • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


            Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


            To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




            draft saved


            draft discarded














            StackExchange.ready(
            function () {
            StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3181739%2funderstanding-the-implication-of-what-well-defined-means-for-the-operation-in%23new-answer', 'question_page');
            }
            );

            Post as a guest















            Required, but never shown





















































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown

































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown







            Popular posts from this blog

            Taj Mahal Inhaltsverzeichnis Aufbau | Geschichte | 350-Jahr-Feier | Heutige Bedeutung | Siehe auch |...

            Baia Sprie Cuprins Etimologie | Istorie | Demografie | Politică și administrație | Arii naturale...

            Nicolae Petrescu-Găină Cuprins Biografie | Opera | In memoriam | Varia | Controverse, incertitudini...